15001518121809920.pdf

(208 KB) Pobierz
Nanoethics (2011) 5:295–307
DOI 10.1007/s11569-011-0133-z
ORIGINAL PAPER
The Social and Ethical Acceptability of NBICs for Purposes
of Human Enhancement: Why Does the Debate Remain
Mired in Impasse?
Jean-Pierre Béland
&
Johane Patenaude
&
Georges A. Legault
&
Patrick Boissy
&
Monelle Parent
Received: 4 August 2011 / Accepted: 16 October 2011 / Published online: 11 November 2011
#
The Author(s) 2011. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com
Abstract
The emergence and development of con-
vergent technologies for the purpose of improving
human performance, including nanotechnology, bio-
technology, information sciences, and cognitive sci-
ence (NBICs), open up new horizons in the debates
and moral arguments that must be engaged by
philosophers who hope to take seriously the question
of the ethical and social acceptability of these
technologies. This article advances an analysis of the
factors that contribute to confusion and discord on the
topic, in order to help in understanding why argu-
ments that form a part of the debate between trans-
humanism and humanism result in a philosophical
and ethical impasse: 1. The lack of clarity that
emerges from the fact that any given argument
deployed (arguments based on nature and human
nature, dignity, the good life) can serve as the basis
for both the positive and the negative evaluation of
NBICs. 2. The impossibility of providing these
arguments with foundations that will enable others
to deem them acceptable. 3. The difficulty of applying
these same arguments to a specific situation. 4. The
J.-P. Béland (*)
Département des sciences humaines, Université du Québec
à Chicoutimi,
Chicoutimi, Québec, Canada G7H 2B1
e-mail: jpbeland@uqac.ca
J. Patenaude
:
G. A. Legault
:
P. Boissy
:
M. Parent
Université de Sherbrooke,
Sherbrooke, Québec, Canada
ineffectiveness of moral argument in a democratic
society. The present effort at communication about
the difficulties of the argumentation process is
intended as a necessary first step towards developing
an interdisciplinary response to those difficulties.
Keywords
Debate about transhumanism and
humanism . Human enhancement . Philosophical-
ethical impasse . Social-ethical acceptance
The emergence and development of convergent
technologies for the purpose of improving human
performance [33], including nanotechnology, biotech-
nology, information technology, and cognitive science
(NBICs), open up new horizons in the debates and
moral arguments that must be engaged by philoso-
phers who hope to take seriously the question of the
ethical and social acceptability of these technologies.
Debates over the convergence of NBICs for the
purpose of human enhancement often entail the
following polarization:
On one side are those who are
‘unconditionally
for’,
the people known as transhumanists, such as Naam
[27], Bostrom [5] and Kurzweil [22]. These
authors invoke moral arguments related to freedom
and autonomy, nature and human nature, to legiti-
mize the position that the only way for human beings
to escape human incompleteness is to implement
the convergence of technologies on the nano
296
Nanoethics (2011) 5:295–307
scale, thus making it possible to surmount
biological limitations (the fragility of being;
disease and death) until the coming of the
human-machine hybrid or immortal cyborg—the
posthuman [19].
On the other side are those who are
‘uncondi-
tionally against’, commonly known as the
humanists, like Fukuyama [15,
16]
and
Habermas [18]. These authors reply by wielding
the semantic incompatibility of moral arguments
based on the nature, dignity, and good life of
fragile mortal human beings as evidence of
limitations that it is appropriate to impose in
order to restrain, indeed altogether prohibit, the
development of these new nanotechnological
powers in order to alter human beings and thus
dominate first human nature and then nature as a
whole.
arguments, our analysis will show how four factors help
us understand why the debate between transhumanism
and humanism has been incapable of a productive
outcome.
1. The ambiguity that results from the fact that a
single deployed argument (nature and human
nature; dignity; the good life) can serve as the
basis for both a positive and negative evaluation
of the development of NBICs, because the core
meaning of the argument’s moral utterance is not
specified.
2. The impossibility of providing these arguments
with foundations that will enable others to deem
them acceptable.
3. The difficulty of applying these arguments to a
specific situation.
4. The ineffectiveness of moral argument in a
democratic society.
To undertake this philosophical process of clarifi-
cation, it was necessary to examine all the texts
published in the journal
NanoEthics
since it was
founded in 2007. From among these texts, we
retained 14, based on two criteria: articles that discuss
moral arguments in favor of or against nanotechnol-
ogies; and articles on meta-ethics. We also analyzed
reports (including the National Science Foundation
Report, [1]) and recent books that met the same
criteria.
As has been pointed out by Jean-Pierre Dupuy
[14], philosophical debates on the ethical foundations
of nanotechnologies have become so routine that one
could number the arguments constantly deployed and
observe that when one person invokes Argument
Number Ten, someone else invariably replies with a
corresponding counterargument:
‘The
same argu-
ments are always served up, and they are always
answered with the same counter-arguments’. Why is
the philosophical debate reduced to this clash of
incompatible arguments and counterarguments? In
other words, why has the debate so far been destined
to remain mired in impasse? This is the preliminary
question to which we want to formulate some replies.
If we wish to grasp the relevance of philosophy to
the sphere of the social and ethical acceptability of the
development of new technologies, we must become
familiar with and understand those sources of the
conflict that account for the way the discussion ends
in impasse.
In the present article, we will advance the analysis
presented by Patenaude et al. [30], which identified the
threefold nature of a moral argument, the seven core
meanings of the moral arguments usually deployed in
debate about nanoethics, and the five moral stances that
underlie those seven moral arguments. In the polarized
climate of discussion between transhumanists and
humanists, the main arguments that clash are those based
on: nature and human nature; dignity; the good life;
autonomy; and rights. Focusing exclusively on these
The Arguments’ Ambiguity
The ambiguity of the arguments used (arguments
based on nature and human nature, dignity, and the
good life) in these discussions between humanism and
transhumanism represents one factor contributing to
confusion and philosophical impasse. How are we to
account for this? We can do so using an analytic
model that relies on a definition of the notion of
ambiguity in philosophy.
‘We
are dealing with an
ambiguity when
the word or phrase has more than
one meaning within a given context
and we are
uncertain which one to choose’ ([29]: 107). A model
of this definition appears in Fig.
1
below:
Based on this analytic model, we will see in what
follows that the arguments based on nature and
human nature, dignity, and the good life, as found in
the context of the moral utterances of the moral
Nanoethics (2011) 5:295–307
Argument in the context of debate
297
to protect the values’ associated with human nature
([15]: 218).
Sense B: Critical
Transhumanists like Kurzweil [22]
reply that the essence of the human being resides not in
our limitations, but in our capacity to overcome them:
Then perhaps our basic disagreement is over the
nature of being human. To me, the essence of
being human is not our limitations—although we
do have many—it’s our ability to reach beyond
our limitations. We didn’t stay on the ground. We
didn’t even stay on the planet. And we are already
not settling for the limitations of our biology.
Kurzweil [22] thus prefers openness to human
enhancement by NBICs over a static utopia of human
nature. The biological nature of the human being can
vary without limitations at the whim of the develop-
ment of these convergent technologies (NBICs) of
which it is itself the matrix:
‘[T]here
are no essential
barriers to our emulating these ways in our technol-
ogies, and we are already well down this path.’
Human enhancement by means of the development of
these technologies, carried out in order to transcend
the biological nature of the human being, would thus
have nothing sinister about it. It would be a part of the
tradition of human effort to continue that process of
self-appropriation that is constitutive of humanity. It is
for this reason that prohibiting the development of
NBICs is illegitimate. Thus for the philosopher
Dominique Lecourt [26], as expressed in his book
Humain post humain,
ethics cannot remain limited by
the formulation of prohibitions in the name of human
nature, because the singularity process (the process of
hybridizing the human with the technological) is
constitutive of human nature:
And if we place the human being within the
‘flux
of the living’, as is appropriate, technological
reality cannot be thought about without viewing it
as an essential dimension of human beings, whose
very nature it is to manifest themselves in
perpetual becoming, propelled by an ongoing
constructive and destructive dynamic.
A.
Affirmative, humanist sense
vs
B.
Critical, transhumanist sense
Fig. 1
Model for the analysis of ambiguity in an argument in
the context of debate. A. Affirmative, humanist sense vs B.
Critical, transhumanist sense
arguments advanced in the debate, constitute factors
contributing to ambiguity and discord and lead to
philosophical and ethical impasses.
The Ambiguity of the Argument Based on Nature
and Human Nature
In the argument based on nature and human nature
that makes it possible to evaluate using convergent
NBICs for human enhancement, the core meaning of
the moral utterance is a prescription. This moral
utterance specifies what we must do or not do, taking
into account the knowledge we have of the laws that
govern nature and our own human nature. But the
argument is ambiguous, because it refers to at least
two contradictory justifications for the moral utter-
ance in the context of the debate between humanism
and transhumanism:
Sense A: Humanist
“Nature”
in its religious sense
implies everything God has created, laws that have
been handed down, and the order or plan that serves
as the criterion for judgment. For humanists like
Fukuyama, the human being who has been enhanced
with NBICs, the cyborg that the transhumanist Stock
[35] identifies with the
‘fusion
of technology and
biology’, contradicts this divine and immutable order
of nature. However, it also threatens the Western
secular belief in a
human nature
as provisionally
fixed at the present day, in the sense that it is not
‘infinitely
plastic’ in its biological complexity and can
only vary within a certain range determined by life:
‘Fukuyama
maintains that human nature must be
considered fixed even if it isn’t, because the con-
sequences of extreme human plasticity would be the
disappearance of democratic values’ such as equality
and autonomy ([3]: 263). Democracies can and must
restrict these consequences for human nature:
‘True
freedom means the freedom of political communities
The Impasse
From the ambiguous potential for both sense
A
and
sense
B
to be implied in the argument based on nature
298
Nanoethics (2011) 5:295–307
and human nature flows the fact that this argument
can be used to evaluate the development of NBICs
both positively and negatively. The fullest philosoph-
ical critique of the equivocal interplay between senses
A
and
B
in interpreting the concept of nature,
especially from a moral perspective, is that advanced
by John Stuart Mill ([23]: 672) in his critical essay
entitled
‘Nature’
(published in the posthumous work
Three Essays on Religion,
1874):
The word
‘nature’,
says Mill, has two main senses:
it denotes either the total system of things [both
artificial and natural] and all their properties, or
things the way they would be, absent all human
intervention. The doctrine that recommends that
human beings follow nature is absurd, because a
human being cannot do otherwise. Under the
second sense, the doctrine that recommends that
human beings follow nature, that is, the sponta-
neous [natural] course of things, as a model for
their own actions is irrational and immoral:
irrational because every human action consists of
changing the course of nature thus defined and
every useful action consists of improving it;
immoral because the course of things is full of
events that are unanimously deemed to be odious
when they result from the human will.
The ambiguity of the terms
‘nature’
and
‘human
nature’ creates a dialogical impasse in
the debate between humanism and transhumanism
because it reflects the existence of at least two
contradictory justifications for maintaining that
the moral utterance follows the laws of nature.
So long as there is no philosophical discussion of
the grounds for adopting one conception of nature
over the other, the impasse will persist.
The Ambiguity of the Argument Based on Dignity
In moral utterances of the Kantian kind, we find the
moral prescription that expresses the condition for
possibility of our moral action:
‘Act
in such a manner
that you treat humanity, both in your own person, and
in the person of any other, always at the same time as
an end and never simply as a means’ ([21]: 36).
Robert Theis [37] argues that this formulation of the
categorical imperative, which affirms the status of
humanness as an end in itself, forms the center of
gravity of Kant’s various statements of principle and
duty. On this view, the core meaning of the moral
argument based on dignity is that it is the nature of
humanity, in one’s own person and the person of
others, to be an end. In the debate between humanism
and transhumanism, this type of argument is ambig-
uous, because it can imply at least two contradictory
and incompatible senses:
Sense A: Humanist
Fukuyama [15] invokes the return
of human dignity as a constraint on autonomy in the
Kantian sense:
‘It
is the existence of free will that
leads to Kant’s well-known conclusion that human
beings are always to be treated as ends and not as
means.’ For some humanists, the cyborg (the human-
machine hybrid) manifests as a transgression of the
principle of human beings themselves constituting
ends. Thus dignity consists of making technological
choices founded on morally acceptable goals, in order
not to treat human beings as objects or means but to
treat them, rather, as ends in themselves, in this way
limiting the consequences of those technological
developments that affect our physical, psychological
or cultural identity.
Sense B: Critical
For transhumanists, however, the
natural end of the human being flows from the free
choice to evolve towards conceptions of the cyborg in
order to allow for the fulfillment of the human desire
to be liberated from finiteness (biological limitations,
diseases, death):
‘The
convergence of humanity and
technology seems to be the natural end of moving this
reasoning into the realm of speculation. The concepts
of
“cyborgs”
as technically enhanced humans or as
humanly enhanced technology can be raised’ ([17]:
80). This natural end is associated with the concept of
dignity-autonomy without constraints, which consti-
tutes the condition of a person who is self-
determining by virtue of her or his own nature. On
this view, humans obey only the law they invent. This
law promotes the freedom of human beings in
‘their
capacity for endless reinvention of their way of being
human according to the fulfillments of their specific
genius’ ([26]: 48).
The Impasse
The ambiguity created by the twofold interpretation of
the concept of dignity (senses
A
and
B)
lies at the
Nanoethics (2011) 5:295–307
299
heart of debates between transhumanism and human-
ism and flows thence to be encountered more or less
everywhere. Thus it can be used as a way of
evaluating the NBIC process positively or negatively.
It represents a real problem for the philosopher
Brownsword [6], who wonders whether the normative
invention of nanomedicine is the least of our worries:
The problem is showcased by modern debates
concerning the ethics and regulation of biotech-
nology. Here, the idea of human dignity has
appeared in two very different roles, in the one
case acting in support of individual autonomy
(human dignity as empowerment) and, in the
other case, acting as a constraint on autonomy
(human dignity as constraint).
The impasse can be partly resolved by clarifying
the core meaning of the moral utterance that makes
the appeal to dignity. In the present case, three
different core meanings are referred to: the Kantian
one, the one based on autonomy, and the one based
on rights. Once the core meaning has been clarified,
we can deal with that aspect of the impasse that
relates to the justification for adopting one moral
argument or the other.
The Ambiguity of the Argument Based on the Good
Life
In this same context of debates between humanism
and transhumanism, arguments made on the basis of
the good life seek to evaluate human choices accord-
ing to their consequences for the conditions of human
life. Thus one finds in Paul Ricoeur’s celebrated
definition of the ethical purpose of the good life the
component of individual choice focused on happiness
while taking others and institutions into account:
‘aiming
at the
“good
life” with and for others, in just
institutions’ ([31]: 172). On this view, a moral
evaluation of the good life rests on this question:
What are the consequences of human enhancement by
means of NBICs for the very conditions of life, both
individual and social? For example, what risks to our
current human conditions of life are entailed by
thinking and acting with the idea of creating an
immortal cyborg? Is this notion of transforming
ourselves in order to achieve infinity, with no
biological, cultural, or affective limitations (‘infinite
knowledge, infinite intelligence, infinite beauty,
infinite creativity, and infinite love’) ([22]: 476) in
continuity with our current experience of a happy
human life in the awareness of finiteness and death, or
does it represent a break with it? In the debate
between humanists and transhumanists, the argument
based on the good life is ambiguous because it
invokes at least two contradictory senses:
Sense A: Humanist
What conception of the good life
do humans have? Humanists like Ricoeur generally
adopt a conception of happiness as an ultimate state to
which humanity aspires. Most humanists are in the
habit of opposing the acceptance of finiteness to the
immoderate desire for infiniteness, a boundless desire
that the Greeks denounced as hubris and that causes
humanity to descend into self-destruction and the
failure represented by despair. For the true happiness
of the human being as found in historical and concrete
existence consists not in acting out the immoderate
desire to conquer human finiteness (limitations, aging,
fear of death) in order to achieve infiniteness (the joy
of being infinite and immortal), but in the act of
accepting suffering and finiteness:
‘Man
is the Joy of
Yes in the sadness of the finite’ ([32]: 140).
Humanists in general oppose this argument to
technological rationality, which strikes them as con-
sisting of that ideological degeneration that leads to
existentialist failure (humanity’s self-destruction). For
example,
‘[H]umanist
wisdom requires coming to
terms with the natural finiteness that affects every
human being’ ([4]: 64), because the paradoxical self-
suppression of both the self and the world flows from
our scientific world, which attends to human beings’
imaginary needs and limitless desires to transcend
finiteness in order to carry out our transformation into
an immortal cyborg.
‘Posthuman
utopias derive from
a similar ambition. What is strange is that some
people don’t hesitate to defend the paradox that
consists of associating the future good life with the
disappearance of humans as they are now’ ([4]: 23).
As Comte-Sponville ([10]: 37; [9]: 251) puts it,
‘What
then can we hope for? Nothing beyond death, so
nothing absolute: any contentment of mortals is
mortal, and life, if it is worth anything, is only worth
something in its finiteness.’
Sense B: Critical
In the transhumanist perspective of
Stock [36], however, the unhappiness of life consists
of continuing to resemble cavemen.
‘But
this lack of
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin